Language in Environmentalism and the Idea of Public Reason
By: Michelle Bastien
When
you and I, as ordinary citizens (assuming of course that you are an ordinary
citizen), sit down and chat about the current environmental issues, we speak in
a very specific language. This language
is not technical or academic, per say, however this language has jargon; words such
as “environmental impact”, “sustainability”, “pristine wilderness”, and “biodiversity”. These terms mean something specific in regards
to our discussion, they convey a certain argument or position. Proper understanding of environmental jargon
is important because it influences many of our decisions as consumers, as
political beings and/or as business owners.
Yet, our specific definition for these words varies, which inevitably creates
ambiguity in the terminology when it stands alone. What I
consider sustainable environmental practices may not be what you consider sustainable. Yet the term “sustainable” can be applied in
both of our environmental philosophies despite the fact that we hold differing
positions. This is frustrating when one
tries to really understand an environmental position, however this language
serves a very specific function in our democratic society and there is a reason
for the existing ambiguity. Exactly what
that function is, I hope to answer by the end of this piece.
First
of all, what do I mean by “environmental language”? Environmental language, as I define it, is
more than just the buzzwords we are so habituated to hearing and using. This language comes with a structure of argumentation. People expect that you present your environmental
“facts” with a kind of scientific objectivity.
Public arguments hinge on the causal relationships outlined between human
action and negative impact: this human action will cause this environmental
impact (insert scientific evidence here).
Therefore, it is bad. Or the
reverse: this change in our human action will cause a reduction or elimination
of this negative environmental impact (insert scientific evidence here). Therefore, it is good.
The
following is a simple example of an environmental argument. I pulled these arguments from Mainstream
Canada’s and the Friends of the Clayoquot Sound’s (FoCS) websites. These examples are meant to demonstrate that
from a listener’s point of view both positions seem rational and scientifically
reasonable. Yet, they make opposing
claims on the impact of open net fishing.
Mainstream
Canada claims that placing open net aquacultures in strong currents allows the ocean
floors to regenerate more efficiently.
The strong current disperses the food and fish waste over a larger, yet
still localized, surface area. The
larger surface area reduces the smothering effect where the waste settles on
the ocean floor. To further reduce their
impact, Mainstream Canada cycles through their cages in order to allow the ocean
floor to fully regenerate itself from the deposits. In their words: “Salmon waste and uneaten
feed on the ocean floor can cause temporary oxygen reduction and other chemical
changes as they decompose, and may cause an increase in the concentration of
metals such as copper or zinc. For this reason, salmon farms are situated
in deep waters with sufficient current to disperse organic wastes” (Mainstream 2012). Being conscious of these impacts and
structuring their practices in order to reduce and eliminate these
environmental impacts, Mainstream Canada prides themselves for being
sustainable.
Where
as FoCS claims that these strong tidal flows are an environmental hazard
because the diseases and contaminants, that inevitably emerges from these
cages, can travel kilometres. This
increases the potential of infecting the wild salmon population: “because salmon farms are located in
areas with strong tidal flow to disperse the feces from hundreds of thousands
of fish contained in close proximity, these same tidal currents can spread
viral particles many kilometres” (FoCS 2012).
Concluding that Mainstream Canada is an
unsustainable industry. FoCS says: “There are many environmental and
economic impacts associated with the practice of open net-cage salmon
aquaculture, but of particular concern are a number of deadly salmon viruses”
(FoCS 2012). Pay particular attention to
the quotes provided and notice that the structure of the language is
similar. Both parties have identified a
causal relationship between a human action and a particular outcome. On the one hand, a strong tidal current
disperses the organic wastes, and on the other strong tidal currents spreads
diseases. The goal of this piece is not
for you the reader to decide whose side you stand on, that is besides the
point. The point is to make light of the
fact that both parties use the same language in order to publicly present their
argument. Let us be frank: the “science”
behind these arguments is not the originating reason for these group’s passions.
Mainstream Canada and FoCS have their
own reasons for being present in our cultures, neither of which is in the name
of science. Let us quickly identify the
systems of values that can be found imbedded within the superficial language of
environmentalism.
Mainstream
Canada defines sustainability as being able to “operate in such a way that
[they] do not reduce the potential for future food production based on the same
natural resources” (Mainstream 2012). They
go on to say “sustainability is a goal that relies on balancing environmental,
social and economic benefits and impacts, with a long-term commitment for
continual improvement” (Mainstream 2012). There are two important ideas that I would
like to draw from the above statements: 1) Mainstream Canada distinguishes the
idea of environmental sustainability from
the larger concept of sustainability. For Mainstream Canada, environmental is only
one leg of the tripod model of sustainability and the environmental leg is
largely to keep the two other legs standing.
If aquaculture permanently and irrevocably damages ocean waters, then economic
opportunities will be lost which will lead to un-employment and the chain
reaction becomes socially and economically systemic. In other words, their values gravitate towards
economic successes.
On
the other hand, FoCS have a very different philosophy of sustainability and it
revolves around the idea of a pristine wilderness. In gross: if it was not there before, it
should not be here at all. Therefore,
anything people put in the ocean waters is un-sustainable. They act on visibility and aesthetics and
strongly believe in the idea that nature knows best.
This
clash in system of values in environmentalism is analogous to the clash in the
systems of values in politics. John
Rawls points out in his article “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited” that a
natural outcome of a “well ordered constitutional democratic society” (Rawls
765) is the idea of public reason. He
says: “This is because a basic feature of democracy is the fact of reasonable
pluralism—the fact that a plurality of conflicting reasonable comprehensive
doctrines, religious, philosophical, and moral, is the normal result of its
culture of free institutions” (Rawls 765-766).
Basically, the idea of public reason is the idea that citizens need to
have a universal and neutral language in order to discuss contentious issues,
like environmentalism. An example
provided by Rawls clarifies his position quite well.
In
1784-1785 there was a famous debate between Patrick Henry and James Madison. This debate dealt with the question as to
whether or not religion should be incorporated in public schools. The interesting aspect of this debate is the
fact that it “was argued almost entirely by reference to political values
alone” (Rawls 794). Christian knowledge
was argued to be “an effective way to achieve basic political values, namely,
the good and peaceable conduct of citizens” (Rawls 794). Christian knowledge was not defended to be
“good in itself” because to argue on such grounds requires that the listeners
are themselves Christians. For Rawls, it
is only sensible and natural that politics, in a liberal democracy, has
developed a shared language with its own structure of argumentation and
jargon. This is no different in
environmentalism.
The
voice of science seems to have been adopted as the universal voice, as it
appears to be void of any particular system of value. In other words, it has become the public
reason and that is why as listener’s we need to be attentive to an
environmental argument. Superficially,
they will all seem scientifically sound and rational. It is up to you to scratch the surface in
order to have a better understanding of a particular position.
No comments:
Post a Comment